Image and Narrative
Online Magazine of the Visual Narrative - ISSN 1780-678X
 

Home

 

Home archive

 

 

 

Issue 8. Mélanges/Miscellaneous

What is an image and what is image power?

Author: Dirk J VAN DEN BERG
Published: May 2004

Abstract (E): Despite its status as contested discipline, art historiography may be of assistance to visual culture stu­dies in answering the call for a fundamental reconsideration of the prolific picture category of visual imagery within the broad image domain. As a strategy of ideological resistance, reconsideration of this category is essential in order to counter entrenched tendencies such as popular "picture theories of visual perception", the pervasive "picturalising" of non-pictorial image categories and ocularcen­trism’s ideological authority.

Abstract (F): Bien qu’elle soit une discipline de plus en plus contestée, l’histoire de l’art peut rendre de grands services aux études visuelles (« visual culture studies ») en apportant des réponses aux questions relatives à la définition de la notion d’ « image » qui à la fois se mutliplie et se brouille dans le domaine de la culture visuelle. L’étude renouvelée de la notion d’ « image » relève d’une manière de résistance idéologique et s’oppose à toute une série de tendances complices qui se généralisent aujourd’hui : les théories « imagées » de la perception visuelle, la « picturalisation » des catégories non-visuelles ou encore l’autorité idéologique de l’ocularocentrisme.

Key words: Art history, power of images, visual studies, visual perception, ocularocentrism

 

Figure 1Figure 2Figure 3Figure 4

On occasion seemingly innocent questions may have the effect of opening the proverbial can of worms -- uncovering underlying issues, making us aware of crucial issues obfuscated by technical jargon and popular opinion. Food for thought, such questions are worth pondering. They often come to haunt us, frequently fostering heated discussions and affording the persuasive nuancing of points of view when clashing critical positions are being debated. Human vision or the visual experience of the environment being naively self-evident to the sighted, everyone seems to have an answer ready, unaware about the minefield of issues at stake in the question: "what is an image?" (cf Mitchell 1984, Boehm 1994).

The opening questions of the title will be answered below with a number of theses calculated to counter commonly held received ideas or mistaken opinions regarding visual images and imagery. Provocatively simplified to foreground the ideological complications of doxa, the theses' primary aim is to recommend certain contributions from the discipline of art historiography to burgeoning critical and inter-disciplinary interactions collectively sailing under the flag of "culture studies". At the outset care should be taken to distinguish new multi-disciplinary formations from conservative schools of "cultural history". The latter include established approaches to intellectual historiography, Kulturgeschichte or Geistesgeschichte. The contributions of numerous art historians in this regard are based on path-breaking work by nineteenth- and twentieth-century scholars on the humanist legacy of classical antiquity and Renais­sance art, among others by Jacob Burckhardt and Erwin Panofsky. In recent years the initiative within this school has shifted decisively towards a Warburgian kulturwis­senschaftliche (cultural anthropological) critique of the classical legacy in Western cultural memory.[1]

Gaining momentum towards the close of the twentieth century, critical impulses asso­ciated with a series of radical turns and transformations in several discourses[2] challenged the soundness of erstwhile authoritative ideas and assumptions concerning "art" and "culture". Varied reactions to late modernist Bilderflut conditions (the pervasive deluge of images proliferating in the mass media of advanced capitalist societies' culture industries) featured prominently among impulses toward post­modern deconstruction. The overwhelming intensity of visual image production, reproduction, transmission and dissemination in global mass media networks resulted in extreme degrees of visual saturation, threatening literacy in the Gutenberg galaxy, especially culturally literate intercourse with visual images from the elite or high art, past and present (cf Kaufmann 1988).

Similar to the neighbouring areas of philosophical, historical and literary studies, the art historical discipline saw the slaying of former holy cows in the wake of post­modern turns. A foundational set of systematic categories -- the conceptual frame­work sustaining the discipline's inherent biases and partialities -- has become sus­pect, increasingly considered to be tainted or severely compromised by its philoso­phical and historical roots in the global Aufklärung project of modernity (an as yet incompleted project according to Jürgen Habermas 1987). The questioning title of Hans Belting (1987) -- The end of art history? -- clearly encapsulates the perceived consequences of an ideologically-burdened categorial framework directing modern research programmes as well as curatorial practices in humanistic art historiogaphy.

The following concise catalogue summarises a set of central categories of art historio­graphy that has been shaken if not pulled down as former pillars in the disciplinary edifice:

Western aesthetics as one sector in the project of modernity

Conceived as a special mode of subjective human experience, derived from earlier ideas concerning divine or cosmic beauty and the sublime, and evolved as distinc­tive civilised form of disinterested, apolitical or non-ideological contemplation of works and performances of the fine arts. This category is increasingly being chal­lenged by diverse critical calls for an "aesthetics of ordinariness" or an "end to aesthetics as a theory of art".

The Western system of "fine arts"

Viewed exclusively as disciplines of aesthetic production for the creation of works, texts, performances or productions deemed in Western societies to be of elite civilisatory value; elevated and cultivated above lesser, mundane artisanal skills, manual crafts, industrial design, popular culture, mass communication media, entertainment technologies or cyberspace sites. This category is increas­ingly being countered with critical questions concerning "no longer fine arts" and even "the dissipation of art".

A globally institutionalised Western "artworld"

Understood as a social network of art institutions providing the infrastructure for the patronage, production and reception of the fine arts, including art academies, galleries, museums, opera houses, concert halls, theatres, publishing houses, auc­tion houses, recording labels, agents, TV channels, production studios, etc. This category is increasingly at odds with the undeniable reality of a profound "com­modification of art".

The Western canon of art

The notion of an ideal, exclusive and cumulative collection of exemplary, authori­tative masterpieces since classical antiquity; divided into ethnic schools of emer­gent national identities; published, exhibited and performed as proof of historical progress along the path of human emancipation measured according to putatively universal norms. "The fall of the canon" has replaced this category in the wake of its condemnation by critics of social privilege and political interests.

Modern artistry

The notion of naturally gifted and original authors of genius, with unique, perso­nal and subjective experiences as the distinctive source of art's expressive mean­ing, serving also as extraordinary, exemplary and celebrated models of authentic humanity or self-fashioned human identities. This category's relevance has been questioned in production- and readerly-based notions of "the death of the author".

The modern work of art

The notion of autonomous, formally aesthetic and context-independent works of art (whether single opus or collective oeuvre) as closed organic wholes, self-referring texts and alternative societal or world symbols. The legitimacy of this special object status is no longer universally accepted. Instead "the demise of the work of art" emerges in many forms, including conceptual art, land art, perfor­mance art, installation art, body art, video art, etc.

The modern reception of art

The idea of free, elective and individual human intercourse with works of art, taken as the schooled and civilised actions of a cultured and privileged social elite, supposedly for purely contemplative, retrospective and emancipatory purposes given the legitimacy of the above categories. It has been replaced by the idea of "the collapse of the avant-garde".

One reaction to the critical deconstruction of art historiography's foundational frame­work or disciplinary discourse has been the transformation (some would rather say the dissipation) of the discipline into visual theory, visual anthropology, media studies and visual culture studies. Initiated by John Berger's Ways of seeing (1972), these new developments imply a massive expansion of the field of study, now embracing all of human visual culture -- in its totality and in its multifarious specifics. The trans­formed discipline daily discovers new and often surprising connections with diverse special fields studying particular aspects of imagery, visualising processes, forms of visual representation, cultural expressions of "visuality" and the imperious hold of "scopic regimes". Sweeping notions of "global visual culture" are replacing former encyclopedic and philosophical ideals regarding a "universal history of art". Nonethe­less, art history's universal museological scope remains effective -- admittedly no longer as normative idealist construct but as an empirical state of affairs resulting from de facto Western domination.

The sole common denominator among multiplying areas and topics of specialisation in the multi-disciplinary study of visuality seems to be rudimentary ideology-critical stances regarding issues of power ("politics") and desire ("erotics"). In general, visual culture studies' main concern is visual representations of race, class and gender -- by far the most popular topics in run-of-the-mill publications. Visual theory tends to be more reflexive, investigating philosophical assumptions steering the critical dis­courses underlying such disciplinary expansion or inter-disciplinary interaction (cf Carter 1990, Bryson et al 1991). Should art historiography indeed be reincarnated in the guise of "visual culture studies" or, at the least, remain cognisant of its new situa­tion in this inter-disciplinary constellation, it will have to be in dual capacity -- as "theory of images" (Bildwissenschaft) and "history of images" (Bildgeschichte).[3] Interpretation of images that incorporates both theory and history in cultural analysis is essential for the success of art historiographical involvement in cultural studies.

Transforming "art history" into an "expanded history of images" has not proceeded without negative effects. Particularly frustrating is the extreme degree of fragmenta­tion of a vastly expanded empirical field of visual material, all but unsurveyable in its limitless dilation and its interminable stream of local case studies involving countless special interests. The likelihood is real of visual culture studies degenerating into a "free-for-all" squatters' area, as is its exploitation by intreprenieurial and activist researchers from formerly powerful disciplines (for instance, departments of English, history and anthropology), particularly when the critical stance is driven primarily by political and financial allegiances, ideologically untempered by self-critical and syste­matic questioning. The provocative "Visual culture questionnaire" (October 1996) re­vealed that a likely outcome of this situation may well be that we are preparing a new generation of proficient consumers of visual culture rather than informed and passio­nate critics of exploitative culture industry and mass communication media.

Against this background one may indeed pose the question: What could a question­able art historiography (an essentially contested and disputed discipline as suggested above) contribute to the new field of visual culture studies? What could be considered as the art historian's typical contribution to interdisciplinary investigations of visual material? In this regard I want to single out one attribute of art historians -- their visual expertise. Their schooling is primarily a matter of acquiring an educated, expe­rienced eye and a committed imagination as demonstrated, for example, by the nine­teenth-century flourishing of museum-based Kunstkennerschaft. From the time that connoisseurs began specialising in the "attribution" and "authentication" of works of art on the basis of the expert eye's ability to detect unique artistic "hands", profes­sional art historians were expected to have mastered and refined advanced and specia­lised forms of "visual literacy".

Certain components of art historians' visual expertise were held in common with col­leagues in other empirical disciplines. Two of these may be singled out:

Committed observation

This concerns an analytical mode of looking where the expert's professional repu­tation is at stake in findings dependent on accuracy of observation. It typically entails dialectical movement between two extremes: "I trust the evidence of my own eyes, one has to believe in what can be seen" as opposed to "I distrust my eyes, one has to be suspicious about visible evidence". The rapid development and application of increasingly sophisticated instruments and technologies of visual analysis heighten rather than resolve this tension. The opposing positions share the assumption that visual material provides sensory access to all of reality, seeing visible traces as signs affording the interpretation of diverse invisible conditions and factors (cf Nadin 1984).

Close scrutiny

Such analytical procedures and protocols include the acute scrutiny of details, an experienced awareness of visual media's material conditions and technical fea­tures, a sensitivity for changing contexts of image production, reproduction, dis­play and reception. Similar to many other disciplines where the mainstream was once ruled by the positivist paradigm, art historical identification, analysis, com­parison and taxonomic classification are based on empirical observation, case studies and the application of constantly advancing analytical instruments and technologies (such as microscopy, radioscopy, chemical analysis, dendrochro­nology, etc).

However, there are more complex forms of vision associated with competencies that are unique to the discipline of art history. Among these the following warrant special mention:

Personal imaginative appropriation

An art historian's appropriation of works of visual art typically involves at least two related actions. The first may be described as a repeated, lingering, prolonged yet concentrated, retentive-projective inspection of images in works of art, based expressly on personal remembrance of singular images as well as connections discovered between such images, traces of which are held in visual memory once the images have been appropriated. The second involves a special mode of intui­tive spectatorship in which the imagination's consciously playful attention guides the scansion of images. This is grounded in a deep-seated awareness of visual material's fundamental ambivalence. The play of ambiguity is an objective feature of images that has always enthralled visual artists who explore it in often surpris­ing ways in works of art, hence calling for appropriately nuances responses from imaginatively aware spectators. Methodical doubt as to the reliability of observa­tion thus gives way to critical alertness regarding ideological effects either con­cealed or revealed, repressed or propagated by visual images -- a critical alertness that may be compared with Paul Ricoeur's "hermeneutics of suspicion".

Visual hermeneutics

Art historical spectatorship is characterised by singular visualising processes -- probably constituting the core of a discipline that is known for special modes of visual rumination which involve "imaginal" or "imagistic" discourses that fre­quently test the limits of everyday ratiocinative procedures. Such imaginative acts of visual musing may be described as performances of "image hermeneutics", initiated in response to each work of art's peculiar spectator engagement. Art his­torians apply ordinary methods of scholarly investigation -- the customary heuris­tic, contextualising, comparative, analytical or critical procedures. However, such procedures are often performed as imaginative visualisations, discovering allusive relations within and among images, progressively assembling metaphorical refe­rences in interaction with, yet also parallel to or beyond verbal texts and dis­courses.[4]

Such acts of imaginative visualising are central to something that, for want of a better term, may be called "iconological discourse" -- in other words, intrinsically visualising forms of argumentation and adumbration in which images do not merely serve to illustrate, exemplify or supplement verbal theorising. As in ordi­nary visual experience, yet with higher levels of reflection and conscious freedom of restraint, the art historian's way of negotiating the world of visuality comprises "hetero-imaginal" movements of visual material. This sets into motion remarkable reverberations in the responsive spectator's imagination, frequently involving unconscious or fantastic imagery, figurative meanings, cognitive schemes, world­views, ideological image values and powers.

A first thesis may be advanced against this background sketch of radical doubts about art historiography's foundational categories as opposed to the discipline's enduring special involvement in the field of visuality. The thesis is prompted by the art histo­rical penchant for approaching any image as if it were a potential work of art requir­ing special attention and imaginative efforts of meaning. The notion of investigating how images behave in circumstances approaching the condition of art emanates from a crucial position in philosophical anthropology which finds the embodied human imagination a more convincing basis for the global scope of visual culture studies than sensory perception, species-specific optics or neurological "hard-wiring" (cf Kearney 1988).

Thesis 1

The central category at the very core of visual culture studies, "image" (including its cognates Bild, beeld, imago, eikon and their derivatives) is completely polysemic and utterly ambiguous. The incredible diversity of the image domain, coupled with the inherent ambivalence of any individual image, surpass anything we might imagine -- one reason for the persistent recurrence of image suspicion, as displayed in historical instances of repression, censure and destruction of images.

Three exemplary cases may be cited to convey some idea of the diversity and ambi­guity of image categories. They represent undertakings, from different points of view, to map the varied classes within the broad domain of the image.

The first example concerns a leading figure in perception psychology, J J Gibson, who put forward the notion of "perception as environmental systems". Gibson (1971, 1978 & 1979) challenges a prevailing concept -- the "arrested image" according to his terminology -- with a contrasting critical idea of "progressive image formation". He bases his critique on the progressive processing of "information contained in the ambient optic array", immediately accessible in the optic field of bodily mobile sentient beings moving through the visual world with its relatively constant "affor­dances" (such as the horizon, angles, surfaces and gradings). Gibson claims that sur­faces have actually perceived "affordance meaning" while the marks on a surface may have "referential meanings", provided they are produced by a "graphic act" and re-ceived by an "imaginative act". His insistence on surfaces or screens as image carriers is significant (cf Steer 1989, Costall 1990). It is a valuable reminder that every image represents something in some respect and for somebody, hence necessitating media of representation (cf Sparshott 1983). Actions of human representation and mediation count among the essential conditions of imagery, even to the extent that the embodied human selfhood -- itself an image, an image bearer and a position of image formation and habituation -- may be taken as the destination of imagery.

Gibson (1980: xv-xvii) broadly distinguishes ten kinds of visual image:

* Solid images -- three-dimensional objects like sculptural pieces, statues, models or toys.

* Pictorial images -- pictures, paintings, drawings, engravings, photographic prints, projected slides or shadow-casters like low or high relief.

* Arrested images -- "many would assume that this is the only kind of image, but it is not", the counter example is progressive screen images like Oriental shadow-play and cinematic images.

* Mirror images -- virtual objects or scenes behind smooth reflective surfaces.

* Projected camera images (camera obscura) -- pictures formed on the inner surface of a dark chamber with a pinhole or lense in the opposite wall.

* Photographic camera images (camera lucida) -- camera images arrested by a shutter, latent image in emulsion, negative image on film and positive image on another surface.

* Retinal images -- "a vague term that covers up the prevalent confusion about vision in physiology and psychology" (Gibson 1980: xvi); an optical image on the inner surface of the dark chamber of the vertebrate eye (false analogy with the camera obscura), or a physiological image in the mosaic of photoreceptors of the retina transmitted to the brain (false analogy with a latent arested image in photo­graphic emulsion).

* Optical after-images -- "supposedly the after-sensation of overstimulating the photoreceptors", or of prolonged stimulation of them, with a fixated eye".

* Memory images -- "taken to be the trace of an arrested physiological image that has been transmitted to the brain"

* Mental images -- "a little-understood kind of experience"; we do not have tiny observers in our heads but, "if not an image, what is the experience to be called?" Dream images, imaginary fantasies, metaphorical imagery, mind's eye images, schemes of thought?

The diversity of the classes of images in Gibson's list is noteworthy as well as the fact that the sequence of items included in his catalogue comprises an argument in critique of "arrested images" and "retinal images". As will become evident, the latter category confusion is widespread and by no means restricted to psychology and physiology (cf Barlow et al 1990).

The prolific author, James Elkins, an American art historian trained as a painter, pro­vides a second example. He positions himself as a critic of semiotic image categories, particularly the popular Peirceian notion of the image as icon in distinction from index and symbol. He aspires to grasp the "sub-semiotic basis" of visual material that resists semiotic classification as signs. His writings converge on the undefinable conceptual core of his line of reasoning -- "the image as material trace". The choice of examples and his analyses are therefore calculated to deliberately stretch or torture semiotic categories to the breaking point.

Opting for the generic term gramma (indicating a common origin in interlacings of writing, notation and picturing), Elkins (1999) distinguishes seven kinds within the domain of the image. The critical aim of his classification of images is significant, since the term gramma evidently engages Gibson's lapidary phrase "marks on a sur­face". Disregarding ideal-typical cases of "pure pictoriality" and "pure (alphabetic) writing", Elkins presses and worries the outer and inner limits of this single Gibson category by analising some rather perplexing variants of the "pictorial image":

* Allographs / allomorphs --

A variant of a morpheme that leaves its syntactic function intact. Calligraphy, typography, paleography and layout produce allomorphic alternations or elabora­tions of characters and entire scripts (the sum total of changes that can be made to letters without affecting their alphabetic identities). Typical examples include calligraphy as style, autograph and signature, and the page as a picture.

* Semasiographs (as opposed to glottographs) --

A sign that does not denote sounds in spoken language. Hieroglyphics, pictogra­phic scripts, pictorial elements as writing are typical examples.

* Pseudowriting --

Any set of disjunct signs that appears to be writing but cannot function as a record of a language or as a transcription of a full system of writing. A typical case would be indecipherable scribbled imitations of cursive writing found in paleo­graphy.

* Subgraphemics --

Pictures comprised of asyntactic signs; the study of images whose signs are dis­joint yet lacking formatting or syntactic order -- either picture-writing (pictures whose signs can be read as sentences or narratives) or pseudo-picture-writing.

* Hypographemics --

The study of images comprised of non-disjoint signs -- either "pure pictures" or perfect holograms, or apparently multiple signs (as in some petroglyphs), or appa­rently single, isolated or fused signs (hypograms as in potter's marks). These include images that seem like they might be read but lack a disjoint signary.

* Emblemata --

Pictures accompanied by texts (for instance an illustration with caption, a picture with legend or an advertisement copy with slogan). Early modern emblems com­prised of three components -- a pictura/icon/imago, an inscriptio/motto/lemma, and a subscriptio/declaratio/epigramma. Typical examples are from heraldry and from word & image studies.

* Schemata --

Images comprising pictures, writing and notation, usually based on reference lines (like graphs) and other geometric configurations. In philosophy schemata refer to images taken to be poised between perfect reproductive versimilitude and perfect ideational abstraction.

The notion that "the object stares back", advanced and explored in Elkins (1997), em­phasises image power as the uncontrollable effect or hold that images have on the imagination of spectators. Thus "affective image" may be taken as his core concept.

A third case is W J T Mitchell, one of the pioneers of visual theory and of a post­structuralist "picto­rial turn" in the USA. As literary scholar he developed his concepts from oppositions of word and image --- from the ancient power struggle between verbal and visual processes of signification. Less specialised in the areas of perceptual and pictorial imagery, his conception of the domain of images is much broader than that of either Gibson or Elkins. Mitchell (1986: 10) proposes a "family of images" covering the field of visuality in five branches: graphic images (pictures, statues, designs), optical images (mirrors, projections), perceptual images (sense data, "species", appearances), mental images (dreams, memories, ideas, fantasmata) and verbal images (metaphors, descriptions), summarised in the Mitchell's well-known table:

 

The three examples of image classifications reviewed above are not intended to cover the whole image domain systematically, nor are they meant to pursue countless histo­rical variations in visual culture. They nonetheless reveal the effects of ideological and discursive interests on systematic distinctions between various kinds of imagery. A second thesis rises from the ideologising of the diversity of image concepts and radical ambiguity and polyvalency of images:

Thesis 2

As modern Westernised people, all of us, against our will, are victims of reduced yet popular "picture theories of perception". As a consequence we are always already ideologically infected in our own bodies, ideologically obsessed even in our most personal and private experience ("nobody can see for or on behalf of somebody else").

As a rule, human production and reception of images in visually mediated communi­cation implicate the full range of slippery image categories distinguished among Gib­son, Elkins and Mitchell. Each action may be initiated by a specific kind of image but any serious engagement with imagery will eventually generate connections between diverse categories. Despite this principal assumption we nonetheless have at our dis­posal only extremely reduced conceptions of the image. As historical subjects of prevailing modern "scopic regimes" -- recall Heidegger's (1977) striking description of modernity as der Zeitalter der Weltbild ("the age of the world picture") -- we are deeply embroiled in Western ideological culture and cannot escape its effects. In general, we have come to conceive and experience the spectrum of image categories one-sidedly on the spatial model of graphic images and, even more reductively, on the picture as a technical variety of graphic image -- in effect "picturing vision" in a literal sense (Snyder 1980).

In the West, pictures attained model status as rationalising agents in the aftermath of the Renaissance. Accordingly, the "picture" ("graphic image" or Gibson's "arrested image") began "colonising" the spectrum of image categories -- the pictorial model extending its influence from left to right in terms of Mitchell's "family of images" in the table above. "The age of the world picture" germinated during the early modern era, before experimental science, mathematical construction, technological design, pictorial art and narrative rhetoric differentiated into separate disciplines of knowl­edge, each involving its own modern social institutions. During the Renaissance the picture category derived its model status from its historical positioning at points of intersection between these areas of cultural change.

Inspired by the search for scientific knowledge and a desire for technological control, early modern optics discovered various mechanical analogies between the human eye and new optical instruments of scientific observation such as the camera obscura, telescope and microscope. On the basis of these mechanical analogies epoch-making connections were established between optical or retinal images and pictures made by human hands. Such analogies are evidently the topic of an eighteenth-century compa­rison of the human eye and the camera obscura (Figure 1). Johannes Kepler was merely the first of many to define the optical image as a reversed or upside-down picture (pictura), establishing analogies between optical configurations in the retinal mosaic and the perspectival design of graphic images or pictures (cf Lindberg 1982, Lepsky 1986, Panofsky 1991, Damisch 1994). The picture's expanding scope in "mo­dernising vision" during "the age of the world picture" dilated from the composition of paintings to the system of mapping co-ordinates in cartography, the axis system of graphic charting or diagramming, the registration of camera images, the projection of film images on cinematic screens or television tubes, the digital design of computer graphics to various formats of digital imaging on monitor screens. These techno­logical advances are indicative as well of escalating degrees of mechanisation and industrialisation of human vision (cf Crary 1988, Debray 1995).

Comparative depiction of the human eye and the camera obscura. Early eighteenth-century book illustration

Figure 1: Comparative depiction of the human eye and the camera obscura. Early eighteenth-century book illustration

With optical image-formation based on the model of anthropogenic pictures, graphic depictions in return are easily conceived in terms of visual perception (taking graphic images as "quasi-percepts").[5] Furthermore, the "picturalising" of image categories was not restricted to the discovery and explication of analogies between pictures and eyes. The "picturalising" of the image domain continued inexorably till the full spectrum of invisible and inner-bodily images were modelled on, or reconceived in pictorial terms -- one reason some prefer "iconicity" as a term for the image domain. The "colonising" process also affected mental and verbal imagery,[6] the images of memory, dreams, metaphors, fictive imaginary fantasies, eidetic or notional images like place and body images, human and gender images, images of the self and of others, role models, corporate images, city images, images of history and of commu­nal destinies, heroes, martyrs and enemies, images of societal order, nature, the world and of the divine, etc.[7] The ideologisation of human culture typically feeds on and exploits such networks and constellations of embodied imagery in the field of visuality. Ideological powers are active in the field of visuality, shaping the produc­tion and reception of symbolic forms of human identity, reflected in the frequently violent cultural dynamic of contesting images of humanity, society, history, the world and the gods or idols. This involves the construction of imaginary fixations whose dis­torting effects are due to their cancer-like growth in the image domain and their relentless dissemination in visual culture.

Such ideological fixations are typically images of "what goes without saying" (Ri­coeur 1986, cf Van den Berg 1993) -- images that empower and disempower, images that conceal and reveal, images that identify and stereotype, images that blind people and that make people see, images that console and images that damn. Spiritual blind­ness, sighted persons who nonetheless do not or wish not to see -- these are apt descriptions of the ideological disabilities of human vision and imagination (meta­phorically similar to pathologies of vision like "blind spots" and "tunnel vision" examined in Elkins 1997). Containing many histories of contested images (cf Mose­neder 1997), visuality in the end belongs to the domain of imago where normative ideological image powers, image values and communal human identities are at stake (cf Marin 1993, Van den Berg 1996: 12-23). In the history of visuality relations between symbolic images of the self and others, images of self-interest and of alien cultures are distorted into ideological confrontations between self-images and threate­ning images of enemies.

Western concepts of picturing or depiction are reductive in unduly emphasising tech­nical procedures of image making, with production aesthetics superseding reception aesthetics. Pictorial images are made by means of iconic reductions -- products of "miniaturising" processes (among others framing cuts, motif selection, scale diminu­tion, reduction of dimensions, decrease of light and colour intensities, exclusion of movement, sound and animation).[8] Of far greater significance, however, is the fact that such reductions enable the users of images to register major advantages, in parti­cular with respect to the objectification, fixation, filtering, ordering and manipulation of visual information as a means of expanding the power of human knowledge and concerted control of the whole of reality.

One of the engines driving this "picturalising of the domain of images" was perspec­tive design (the "fatal triangle" of projective geometry) and, underlying it, Leone Alberti's finestra aperta or open window, picture metaphor. With representation redu­ced to depiction, the depictive image is assumed to be a transparent medium that affords a dominating or controlling survey ("regime") of depicted realities and fictio­nalities. One of the most regularly reproduced images in visual culture textbooks, Albrecht Dürer's renowned wood-cut print of 1525 (Figure 2), offers a classical illus­tration of this notion. Notice the focused concentration and immobilised monocular gaze of the picture maker or draughtsman. A series of pregnant terms may be used to describe this manner of looking. It may be characterised as instrumentally measured, notionally attentive and concentrated staring, as analytically laying bare or dissecting, as rationally synthetising or composing -- in short, exemplifying controlled calcu­lation and objectifying fixation. Such terms all allude to features of a way of seeing that has acquired a certain notoriety in visual culture studies as "the gaze" -- a visual counterpart of the crucial idea that knowledge is power.

Albrecht Dürer (1471-1528), The artist and his model (ca 1527). Wood-cut print from Unterwey­sung der Messung

Figure 2: Albrecht Dürer (1471-1528), The artist and his model (ca 1527). Wood-cut print from Unterwey­sung der Messung

"The gaze" (as opposed to the mobile "glance") may therefore be taken as alternative term for the "picturalising of the domain of images". Its various aspects are revealed in proliferating variations on this theme, for instance "notional gaze", "discursive gaze", "disembodied gaze", "male gaze", "voyeur gaze", "colonial gaze", "flâneur gaze", "tourist gaze", "nostalgic gaze", "paranoid gaze", "logocentric gaze" and "phi­losopher's gaze" (cf Bryson 1983 & 1988, Jay 1986, Olin 1996, Levin 1999). Crucial as a cultural site of ideological power and resistance, the gaze introduces a third thesis:

Thesis 3

As modern people, inhabitants of a globally Westernised world, all of us are at once both practitioners and the victims of ocularcentrism -- the shape of logocentrism in the field of visuality.

The history of technologised picturalising in the image domain is driven by older and more powerful ideological traditions. This is reflected in terms like "the nobility of sight" compared to the other senses (Jonas 1954); the archaic origin of theoretikos as eye-witnessing spectator of divine vision at religious ceremonies (Habermas 1972), and "the modern hegemony of sight" (cf Jay 1986, 1888a & 1988b, Levin 1993). The cardinal role of visual metaphors in defining the validity and legitimacy of scientific or theoretical thought's grasp of self-evident truth in Western rationalism's theo-ontological and metaphysical traditions is common knowledge (cf Rorty 1980, Miles 1985). One merely has to be reminded of the currency and frequency of (dead) meta­phors like "the light of reason", "revelation", "observation", "scrutiny", "insight", "supervision", "seeing through something", "point of view", Wesenschau or "clear and distinct concepts". Twisting the Cartesian cogito ergo sum ("I think, therefore I am"), the motto video ergo sum ("I see, therefore I am") captures this pervasive trend in a terse formulation. It secures the empowered position of knowing subjects over against any object of knowledge, at the same time preserving seemingly opposing ideals of freely adopted alternative points of view versus universal claims, distanced detachment of observation versus metaphysical "presence" -- all based metaphori­cally on aspects of human vision.

Ocularcentrism is so deeply ingrained as a fundamental trait of our ideological culture that its "postmodern deconstruction" tends to similarly conceptualise itself in visual terms, for instance Jean-François Lyotard's figurative use of anamorphosis (the ex­treme perspectival deformation of pictorial images). Certainly one of the best-known examples is Michel Foucault's notion of the "gaze" as panoptic domination. This is based on Jeremy Bentham's Panopticon (Figure 3), an architectural design for a circular prison building, where a single, invisible and omnipotent sentinel in a central tower keeps watch over the many visible and powerless prisoners incarcerated in the circular array of cells. Not confined to penal institutions, the disciplining machinery of vigilant panoptic surveillance eventually "colonised" the clinic, hospital, asylum, boarding school, military barrack, factory floor, administrative head-office and archive. For Foucault (1973 & 1980), the Panopticon's asymmetrical power relations visualise the idea of a "scopic regime of surveillance" -- a new take on the soul's bodily confinement in the dark and phantasmagoric interior of Plato's grotto. This entails a dominant and pervasive system that disempowers human subjects at the point of their visual exposure to others, subjecting their visibility[9] to a disciplining, visualising power whose authority itself is of invisible, discursive origin but, more importantly, internalised by individuals who become their own overseers -- inspecting, guarding and disciplining themselves.

Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), Panopticon (1791)

Figure 3: Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), Panopticon (1791)

The Panopticon represents one of many striking examples of ideological conundrums brought about by complicating connections constructed between diverse areas in the image domain or, to formulate this in another way, puzzling interlacings between various phases of visualising. Mitchell[10] designates such connective images as "hypericons". Examples of such enthralling image nexuses from the history of Wes­tern ocularcentrism include Plato's grotto allegory, empiricist Aristotle's tabula rasa or impressions on an empty wax tablet, the aiming archer's drawn bow as medieval image of intentionality, Locke's dark room (human consciousness as camera obscura), Goethe's "Dann schließe ich die Augen" ("then I closed my eyes") for the physiological generation of entoptic images (Crary 1990), Karl Marx's inverted camera obscura image for false consciousness (Mitchell 1986:168-172), Wittgen­stein's duck-rabbit figure, Sartre's voyeur, the Aura of Walter Benjamin's dialectical images, Richard Kearney's (1987) postmodern "labyrinth of reflecting mirrors" or Martin Jay's (1993) "downcast eyes".

The unfolding of any hypericon entails an arduous, ideologically mapped voyage of exploration, full of twists and turns, through the entire image domain. However, it soon turns out that the picture category's apparently assured status in the image domain is highly questionable. Hence, the picture category has to be fundamentally reconsidered if we are indeed to counter the ideological authority of "picture theories of visual perception", the pervasive "picturalising" of non-pictorial image categories and, finally, the underlying ocularcentrism. Art historiography can assist visual cul­ture studies in this critical task. In itself deeply infected by these ideological distor­tions,[11] art historiography nonetheless is the most experienced discipline in the com­pound undertaking of interpreting pictures, framing theoretical categories and facing ideological powers. Hence my final thesis:

Thesis 4

With the objective of initiating resistance against ocularcentric "scopic regimes" we need dynamic, progressive and action-orientated concepts of the image, appreciating images in temporal and human terms as bodily events which involve ideologically shaped performative acts of the imagination that open picture categories to visual display rhetoric.

A full arsenal of arguments is required to unseat received ideas once they have been firmly established. On this occasion the most rudimentary ideas will have to suffice to outline an alternative perspective on the pictorial image.

Pictures are not merely passive objects of perception. As quasi-subjects they "look back" at us, returning our gazes. As human beings we are not passive recipients of optical stimuli but responsive subjects, responsible for our actions in the field of visuality. We are touched and moved by pictures; they address us, affectively petition­ing our attention. In turn we engage them in imaginative interactions, often even inter­preting them against the grain. Though inanimate, they are animated by our actions; though silent in themselves they "speak to us" when we genuinely engage them. They bodily project imaginary worlds in the eyes of the attentive observer. Undoubtedly graphic images are made by means of iconic reductions that arrest them on spatial screens. Yet they only serve their purposes or begin to approach their completion in spectatorial actions of iconic augmentation.[12] As is the case with all cultural products, pictures are made for us (pro nobis), destined for spectators' imaginative responses. A "stilled" picture (in other words, spatially fixed as motionless, inanimate and silent image) may have a presentational effect of being objectively there, being at once and totally present on its own pictorial terms of reference.[13] In reality, however, pictorial representation comprises extremely nuanced configurations at various levels. Pictures contain clues to be traced, gaps to be filled, connections to be made, ambiguities to be negotiated, games to be played, puzzles to be solved, codes to be deciphered, mean­ings to be construed, conjectures to be tested, positions to be adopted, conclusions to be drawn -- all of this by spectators bodily performing human acts of imaginative appropriation.

Saccadic eye movements of subjects viewing pictures are regularly recorded in per­ception psychology laboratory tests. One such case, the experiments of Alfred Yarbus (1967), may be used to demonstrate aspects of image processing Gibson had in mind with "progressive imagery" (Figure 4). Such mechanical recordings plot optical vision's minute focal area[14] rapidly scanning a picture surface[15] in search of meaning, in each case hunting down clues to answer a particular leading question about the depicted subject matter.[16] Traces of a spectator's bodily interactions with a pictorial image, each recording registers one fleeting moment of "progressive image forma­tion" in the give-and-take between picture and spectator -- each plotting the course of one act in a lasting picture-spectator encounter. Together composing the picture as a performative event, countless such sequences of affective moments and interruptions emerge progressively from repetitive actions of "pictorial generativity" -- a felicitous term for picture-viewing competences put forward in Flint Schier's (1986) Deeper into pictures. Picture-events are infinite in variety. Run-of-the-mill pictures attract no more than a first cursory glance, passing virtually unnoticed, while certain horrific or repulsive pictures cannot even be seen (cf Elkins 1997). Compelling pictures or at times mere arresting pictorial detail[17] may be major incidents leaving the spectator appalled or elated, exhausted or, on extremely rare occasions, in tears, while certain dark or enigmatic pictures may for long refuse communication -- confusing, frustrating, intriging or absorbing their spectators (cf Gröwe 1986).

Recordings of saccadic eye movements scanning Ilya Repin's The unexpected visitor (1884)

Figure 4: Recordings of saccadic eye movements scanning Ilya Repin's The unexpected visitor (1884)

Telling features of pictorial vision are not registered in mechanical recordings of saccadic eye movements. A number of invisible but vision-enabling conditions deserve mention. Pictures and fields of vision never coincide. Thus the spectator always sees more than just a single picture; variable actions, frames and contexts of display rather than isolated and arrested images permeate the individual field of vision. Picture-events as such cannot be recorded. Thus spectators with differing degrees of visual memory are required to start anew with every performance of pictorial spectation or fresh imaginative appropriation. Pictures affect each other, often in surprising ways, whether seen together or in succession, or returning to the same picture after longer or shorter periods of time. Spectators project pictorial images in peripheral vision, held indistinctly as emergent wholes or "schematic maps" (Hochberg 1968), forecasting and foretelling the eventful outcome of a picture performance. This coincides with the progressive collection of visual meaning from the imaginative interplay of visual pro­tension and retension in close readings of pictorial detail.[18] Spectators respond to pictures with imaginative collusion, finding and playing along with imaginary roles pictures project for prospective viewers, gradually fleshing out the contours of appro­priation and critical distance, eventually bonding with, censuring or rejecting the representation.

Conclusion

As such a picture-event represents merely one link, the pictorial manifestation in sub­merged chains of imagery of diverse invisible kinds. When negotiating a picture -- this "surface with markings" -- we thus have to be aware of ideology-infected and embodied networks of images that each individual spectator and subcultural com­munity of spectators, involuntarily contribute to any picture's performativity. This conclusion corroborates that of Hans Belting in his latest publication, Bild-Antropologie (2001). He describes the image sciences' field of investigation as "der Mensch als Ort der Bilder" (the human being as the place of images), the body upon and within which the ideological war of images takes place.

Illustrations

  • Anon. Comparative depiction of the human eye and the camera obscura. Early eighteenth-century book illustration (Crary 1991: 49).
  • Albrecht Dürer (1471-1528), The artist and his model (ca 1527). Wood-cut print from Unterwey­sung der Messung … (Nürnberg: Hieronymus Formschneyder [Andreä), 1538).
  • Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), Panopticon (1791). (Lyon 1994: 64)
  • Recordings of saccadic eye movements scanning Ilya Repin's The unexpected visitor (1884), figure 109 from Yarbus 1967: 174; Frangenberg 1990: 146.

Bibliography

BAL M
2001. Looking in: the art of viewing. Amsterdam: G+B Arts International.

BARLOW H et al
1990. Images and understanding. Thoughts about images, ideas about understanding. Cam­bridge: Cambridge University Press.

BÄTSCHMANN O
1984. Einführung in die kunstgeschichtliche Hermeneutik: Die Auslegung von Bildern. Darm­stadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

BARTHES R
1984. Camera lucida: reflections of photography. London: Flamingo.

BELTING H
1987 (1984). The end of art history? Transl C S Wood. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
2001. Bild-Anthropologie: Entwürfe für ein Bildwissenschaft. Müchen: Fink.

BERGER J
1972. Ways of seeing. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

BOEHM G
1978. Zu einer Hermeneutik des Bildes. Gadamer H-G & Boehm G (Hrsg). 1985. Die Herme­neutik und die Wissenschaften. Frankfurt aM: Suhrkamp: 444-71.

BOEHM G (Hrsg)
1994. Was ist ein Bild? München: Fink.

BREDEKAMP H
2003. A neglected tradition? Art history as Bildwissenschaft. Critical Inquiry 29(3): 418-428.

BRYSON N
1981. Word and image: French painting of the ancien régime. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni­versity Press.
1983. Vision and painting: The logic of the gaze. London: Macmillan.
1988. The gaze in the expanded field. Foster (ed) 1988: 87-114.

BRYSON N, HOLLY M A & MOXEY K (eds)
1991. Visual theory. Painting and interpretation. New York: HarperCollins.

BURKE P
2001. Eyewitnessing. The uses of images as historical evidence. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

CARROLL D (ed)
1990. The states of 'theory': history, art, and critical discourse. New York: Columbia Univer­sity Press.

CARTER M
1990. Framing art. introducing theory and the visual image. Sydney: Hale & Iremonger.

CHEETHAM M, HOLLY M A & MOXEY K (eds)
1998. The 'subjects' of art history: historical objects in contemporary perspectives. New York: Cambridge University Press.

COLLINS C
1991. The poetics of the mind's eye: literaure and the psychology of imagination. Philadel­phia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

COSTALL A P
1990. Seeing through pictures. Word & image 6(3): 273-277.

CRARY J
1988. Modernizing vision. Foster (ed) 1988: 29-50.
1990. Techniques of the observer. On vision and modernity in the nineteenth century. Cam­bridge, Mass: MIT Press.

DAMISCH H
1994. The origin of perspective. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

DEBRAY R
1995. The three ages of looking. Critical Inquiry 21(3): 529-555.

ECO, U
1999. Iconism and hypoicon. Kant and the platypus. Essays on language and cognition. London: Vintage" 337-292.

EDWARDS M
1984. Towards a christian poetics. London: Macmillan.

ELKINS J
1994. The poetics of perspective. Ithaca, NewYork: Cornell University Press.
1997. The object stares back: on the nature of seeing. New York: Simon & Schuster.
1998a. The common origins of pictures, writing, and notation. On pictures and the words that fail them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 163-187.
1998b. The unrepresentable, the unpicturable, the inconceivable, the unseeable. On pictures and the words that fail them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 241-266.

FOSTER H (ed)
1988. Vision and visuality. New York: Dia Art Foundation.

FOUCAULT M
1973. Seeing and knowing. The birth of the clinic. An archaeology of medical perception. London: Tavistock: 107-123.
1980. The eye of power. Power/knowledge. Selected interviews and other writings 1972-1977. Ed C Gordon. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf: 146-165.

FRANGENBERG T
1990. Der Betrachter. Studien zur florentinischen Kunstliteratur des 16. Jahrhunderts. Berlin: Mann.

GASKELL I
1991. History of images. Burke P (ed). 1991. New perspectives on historical writing. Oxford: Polity Press: 168-192.

GIBSON J J
1971. The information available in pictures. Leonardo 4: 27-35.
1978. The ecological approach to the visual perception of pictures. Leonardo 11: 227-235.
1979. The ecological approach to the visual perception. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.
1980. Foreword: A prefatory essay on the perception of surfaces versus the perception of marking on a surface. Hagen (ed) 1980, 1: xi-xviii.

GILL C B (ed)
2000. Time and the image. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

GILMOUR J
1986. Picturing the world. Albany: State University of New York Press.

GRIFFITHS A P (ed)
1987. Contemporary French philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

GRÖWE B
1986. Bilder sehen. Merkur (9/10): 825-44.

HABERMAS J
1972. Knowledge and human interest. London: Heineman.
1987. The normative content of modernity. Outhwaite W (ed) 1996. The Habermas reader. Cambridge: Polity Press: 341-365.

HAGEN M A (ed)
1980. The perception of pictures, 1: Alberti's window: The perspective model of pictorial information; 2: Dürer's devices: beyond the projective model of pictures. New York: Aca­demic Press.

HAGEN M A
1986. Varieties of realism: geometries of representational art. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni­versity Press.

HASENMUELLER C
1981. The function of art as 'iconic text': An alternative strategy for a semiotic of art. Semio­tica 36(1/2): 135-152.
1989. 'A picture is worth a thousand words': How we talk about images. Semiotica 73(3/4): 275-300.

HASKELL F
1993. History and its images: art and the interpretation of the past. New Haven: Yale Univer­sity Press.

HEELAN P A
1985. Perception as a hermeneutical act. Silverman & Ihde (eds) 1985: 43-54.

HEIDEGGER M
1977. The age of the world picture. The question concerning technology and other essays. Transl W Lovitt. New York: Harper & Row: 115-154.

HOCHBERG J
1968. In the mind's eye. Haber R N (ed) 1968. Contemporary theory and research in visual perception. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston: 309-331,

HOY D C (ed)
1986. Foucault. A critical reader. Oxford: Blackwell.

HUBERT BURDA STIFTUNG
2002. Iconic turn - Das neue Bild der Welt. Felix Burda memorial lectures. München: Burda Akademie zum Dritten Jarhtausend. <http://www.iconic-turn.de/>

JAY M
1986. In the empire of the gaze. Foucault and the denigration of vision in twentieth-century French thought. Hoy (ed) 1986: 175-204.
1988a. The rise of hermeneutics and the crisis of ocularcentrism. Poetics today 9: 307-326.
1988b. Scopic regimes of modernity. Foster (ed) 1988: 3-28.
1993. Downcast eyes: the denigration of vision in twentieth-century French thought. Berke­ley: University of California Press.

JONAS H
1954. The nobility of sight. A study in the phenomenology of the senses. Philosophy and Phe­nomenological Research 14: 507-519.

KAUFFMANN G
1988. Die Macht des Bildes: Über die Ursachen der Bilderflut in der modernen Welt. Opla­den: Westdeutscher Verlag.

KEARNEY R
1987. The crisis of the post-modern image. Griffiths (ed) 1987: 112-122.
1988. The wake of imagination: Ideas of creativity in western culture. London: Hutchinson.
1991. Poetics of imagining from Husserl to Lyotard. London: Harper Collins Academic.

KRAUSS R E
1990a. The story of the eye. New Literary History 21(2): 283-98.
1990b. The blink of an eye. Carroll (ed) 1990: 175-199.
1993. The optical unconscious. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

LEPPERT R
1996. Art and the commited eye. The cultural functions of imagery. Boulder, Colorado: West­view Press.

LEPSKY K
1986. Perspektive — Symbol, Konvention, Wirklichkeit. Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allge­meine Kunstwissenschaft 31(2): 214-230.

LEVIN D M
1999. The philosopher's gaze: modernity in the shadows of enlightenment. Berkeley: Univer­sity of California Press.

LEVIN D M (ed)
1993. Modernity and the hegemony of vision. Berkeley: University of California Press.

LINDBERG D C
1982. 1982. Theories of vision from al-Kindi to Kepler. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

LYON D
1994. The electronic eye: the rise of surveillance society. Cambridge: Polity Press.

MARIN L
1993. Des pouvours de l'image. Paris: Seuil.

MELVILLE S & READINGS B (eds)
1995. Vision and textuality. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

MERLIEU-PONTY M
1970. Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

MILES M R
1985. Image as insight. Visual understanding in Western Christianity and secular culture. Boston: Beacon.

MTCHELL W J T (ed)
1980. The language of images. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

MITCHELL W J T
1984. What is an image? New literary history 15(3): 503-37.
1986. Iconology: Image, text, ideology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
1994. Picture theory: essays on verbal and visual representation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

MORRISON K F
1988. 'I am you': The hermeneutics of empathy in Western literature, theology, and art. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

MOSENEDER K (Hrsg)
1997. Streit um Bilder: vom Byzanz bis Duchamp. Berlin: Reimer.

MOXEY K
1994. The practice of theory. Poststructuralism, cultural polics, and art history. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.
2001. The practice of persuasion: paradox and power in art history. Ithaca, New York: Cor­nell University Press.

NADIN M
1984. On the meaning of the visual. Twelve theses regarding the visual and its interpretation. Semiotica 52(3/4): 335-377.

NICHOLSON G
1984. Seeing and reading. Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press International.
1985. Seeing and reading: Aspects of their connection. Silverman & Ihde (eds) 1985: 34-42.

NODINE C A & FISHER D F (eds)
1979. Perception and pictorial representation. New York: Praeger.

NOVITZ D
1977. Pictures and their use in communication. A philosophical essay. The Hague: Nijhoff.

OCTOBER
1996. Visual culture questionnaire. October 77: 25-77.

OLIN M
1996. Gaze. Nelson, R.S. & Shiff, R. (eds). 1996. Critical terms for art history. Chicago: Uni­versity of Chicago Press.

PANOFSKY E
1991. Perspective as symbolic form. New York: Zone Books.

PAULSSON G
1967. Zur Hermeneutik des Anschaulichen in der Bildkunst. Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft 12: 129-153.

PREZIOZI D
1989. Rethinking art history. Meditations on a coy science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

RICOEUR P
1979. The function of fiction in shaping reality. Valdés M J (ed). 1991. ARicoeur reader: Reflection and imagination. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf: 117-136).

RORTY R
1980. Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Oxford: Blackwell.

ROSKILL M
1989. The interpretation of pictures. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.

ROSKILL M & CARRIER D
1983. Truth and falsehood in visual images. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.

SACHS-HOMBACH K & REHKÄMPER K (Hrsg)
1999. Bildgrammatik. Interdisziplinäre Forschungen zur Syntax bildhafter Darstellungs­formen. "bildwissenschaft", 1. Magdeburg: ScriptumVerlag.

SCHIER F
1986. Deeper into pictures. An essay on pictorial representation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

SILBERMAN H J & IHDE D (eds)
1985. Hermeneutics & deconstruction. Albany: State University of New York Press.

SNYDER J
1980. Picturing vision. Mitchell (ed) 1980: 219-247.

SPARSHOTT F E
1983. Preservation, projection, and presence. Preliminaries to a consideration of pictorial representation. Fisher (ed) 1983: 131-46.

STAFFORD B M
1996. Good looking: essays on the virtue of images. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
1999. Visual analogy: consciousness as the art of connecting. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

STEER J
1989. Art history and direct perception: A general view. Art history 12(1): 93-108.

VAN DEN BERG D J
1993. Rhetorical theory and the abiding actuality of pictorial rhetoric. Acta Academica 25(1): 49-82.
1996. A rhetorical typology of traditions of visual power. Acta Academica 28(3): 1-28.

WARTOFSKY M W
1979. Picturing and representing. Nodine & Fisher (eds) 1979: 272-283.
1984. The paradox of painting. Pictorial representation and the dimensionality of visual space. Social research 51(4): 863-883.

WILLEMS G
1989. Anschaulichkeit. Zu Theorie und Geschichte der Wort-Bild-Beziehungen und des litera­rischen Darstellungsstile . Tübingen: Niemeyer.

WOODFIELD R (ed)
2001. Art history as cultural history: Warburg's projects. Amsterdam: G+B Arts Internatio­nal.

YARBUS A L
1967. Eye movements and vision. New York: Plenum.

 

Footnotes

[1] For instance, Aby Warburg's Mnemosyne project or Bilderatlas from the first decades of the twentieth century heralded current practices in visual culture studies such as the use of reproductive images and combining images from art history with contemporary mass media images (cf Woodfield 2001).

[2] Among others the so-called "linguistic turn", structuralist semiotics, poststructuralism, New Histo­ricism and latterly also the "pictorial" or "iconic turn" (cf Foster 1988, Krauss 1993, Mitchell 1994, Melville & Readings 1995, Debray 1995, Leppert 1996, Sachs-Hombach & Rehkämper 1999, Hubert Burda Stiftung 2002).

[3]Bildgeschichte (cf Belting 1994, Gaskell 1991) involves the history of images in general, focusing on changing cultural functions of imagery in an expanded field visual material (cf Leppert 1996, Haskell 1993, Burke 2001), distinct from the confined aesthetic field of art history (cf Roskill & Carrier 1983).

[4] Cf among others Paulsson 1967, Boehm 1978, Bätschmann 1984, Heelan 1985, Morrison 1988.

[5] An understanding of graphic images as "quasi-percepts" is followed almost involuntary by the con­tested idea of depictions as unmediated forms of iconic "presence". The latter is in conflict with the notion of conventional, socially mediated representation, hence the continual contrasting of concepts like index and icon, mimesis and construction, nature and culture, physis en nomos (cf Hasenmueller 1989).

[6] Deeply flawed by the notion of Vorstellungen in the "mind's eye", the mental imagery category has in the wake of nominalism been contaminated by diverse "pictorial" features , for instance by a psycho­logised "quasi-perceptual" comprehension of ideas in empiricist traditions and by rational schemati­cism in idealist traditions (cf Collins 1991). The notion of "logical pictures" in early Wittgenstein's Tractatus offers an extreme example (cf Mitchell 1986: 14-19, Elkins 1999: 57-67).

[7] These various kinds of imagery are intensively explored in art history where they often appear as ideologically charged motifs, topics or themes of modern paintings and sculptural monuments. The notional "picturalising" of "non-pictorial" image categories, on the other hand, explains conceptual mechanisms characteristic of "picture theories of visual perception" -- ideological changes affecting the broad field of visuality at the basis of the history of visual arts.

[8] Bryson (1981) correctly highlights the graphic metaphor of diminution, reduction or "miniaturising". Visual depictions entail technical diminutions, formal reductions or mediated semiotic filtering of visual information. Spatial truncation of dimensions, diminution of scale, loss of tonal intensities, restriction of chromatic range result in the typical pictorial motionlessness, lifelessness, silence or "stillness" -- pictorial qualities at first valued negatively but in due course positively. Initially they were seen as the pictorial art's "deficiencies" that early modern picture makers had to conquer in order to master the "difficulties" of pictorial enargeia as desired quality of imaginary vividness. The modern era revalued this "stillness" as a positive sign of the medium-specific, formally aesthetic, figurative potential of autonomous painting (cf Edwards 1984: 208-10, Morrison 1988: 296-325, Willems 1989).

[9] More accurately, the "visibility" of subjects has to be understood here as discourse's systemic func­tioning, that is as visual representability, "depictabilty" or "picturability", including individual "data-images" in digital data-banks interlinked in the "electronic Panopticon" as investigated by David Lyon in The electronic eye: the rise of surveillance society (1994). Picture archives or image data-banks are thus necessary adjuncts of the panoptic gaze.

[10] According to Mitchell (1986: 5-6) hypericons concern "the way we depict the act of picturing, imagine the activity of imagination, figure the practice of figuration. These doubled pictures, images, and figures [...] are strategies for both giving in to and resisting the temptation to see ideas as images. Plato's cave, Aristotle's wax tablet, Locke's dark room, Wittgenstein's hieroglyphic are all examples of the 'hypericon' that, along with the popular trope of the 'mirror of nature', provide our models for thinking about all sorts of images — mental, verbal, pictorial, and perceptual. They also provide [...] the scenes in which our anxieties about images can express themselves in a variety of iconoclastic discourses, and in which we can rationalize the claim that, whatever images are, ideas are something else."

[11] Cf Preziosi 1989 on the distortive effects of the panoptic gaze and the archives in the discipline, and the debates collected in Bryson et al 1991, Melville & Readings 1995 & Cheetham et al 1998.

[12] Based on François Dagognet's idea of augmentation iconique, Ricoeur proposes a radical revaluation of the idea of miniaturising. Graphic images' iconic functioning resemble the metaphoric processes of imaginative schematising used by Ricoeur to explain fiction's function of world projection. The pain­ters' technical reductions and medial reductions of visuality are seen as systematising and schematising instruments of metaphorical condensation and imaginary world-projection in the pictorial medium: "Thus we are referred to the primary meaning of the word fiction: fictio comes from facere. When the image is made, is is also able to remake the world" (Ricoeur 1979: 129); "Far from yielding less than the original, pictorial activity may be characterized in terms of an 'iconic augmentation', where the strategy of painting, for example, is to reconstruct reality on the basis of a limited optic alphabet. The strategy of contraction and miniaturization yields more by handling less. In this way the main effect of painting is [...] to increase the meaning of the universe by capturing it in the network of its abbreviated signs" (Ricoeur 1976: 420, cf Gilmour 1986: 52-109).

[13] Consider the extreme positions in this regard -- the first of "transparency" where the picture itself becomes "invisible", being replaced by the illusion of the depicted object's "real presence", the second of "opaqueness" or "non-transparency" where the supposedly "non-representative" picture only shows its own means of pictorial design.

[14] The foveal area only comprises about two percent of the field of vision.

[15] Eyes movement consists of approximately four rapid jumps ("saccades") per second, each separated by fleeting moments of rest on certain points ("fixations"). The sequence of saccadic movements and the duration of fixations are involuntary (cf Frangenberg 1990: 144-147).

[16] Yarbus (1967) tested his subjects by asking them seven questions about an image, each question had to be answered within three minutes. In the present connection the kind of questions to be answered from pictures is a major but secondary issue. The point at issue is pictorial imagery's constitution as affording the guided searching function of visual perception.

[17] Cf the sharp distinction Barthes (1984) draws between studium and punctum in the perception of photographic images.

[18] Mostly transpiring below the threshold of consciousness, the steady and dynamic flux of vision's temporal interface between protension and retension releases or impedes anticipated nuances of evasive meaning. The nuances are continually being recalled, retraced, reviewed and reconsidered for possible assimilation into particular picture-events or cumulative appropriations of an image, for example facilitating the reading and interpretation of ambiguous proleptic and analeptic relations of visual narration.

 
 
 

Prof Dirk J van den Berg, Dept of Art History and Visual Culture Studies, University of the Free State, P O Box 339, Bloemfontein 9300, e-mail: vdbergd@hum.uovs.ac.za

   
 

 

Maerlant Center Institute for Cultural Studies

This site is optimized for Netscape 6 and higher

site design: Sara Roegiers @ Maerlantcentrum